အေတြးအေခၚ တန္းတူေက်ာင္းသားေတြ တက္ညီလက္ညီ လက္တြဲႏိူင္ခဲ့ၾကတယ္ ။
ေနဝင္း ေမာင္ေမာင္ ျပဳတ္က်သြားတယ္ ။
သမိုင္းကို ေလ့လာခဲ့သူေတြ စာဖတ္မ်ားသူေတြကို
ဦးေဆာင္တဲ့ေနရာေပးခဲ့ၾကတယ္ ။
နဝတ နအဖ ျဖဳတ္ခ်ဖို ့ ၾကိဳးပန္းခဲ့စဥ္က
NLD လူထုလက္တြဲျပီး ေျမေပၚ ေျမေအာက္ လက္တြဲခဲ့ၾကတယ္ ။
တပ္မေတာ္သားေဟာင္းမ်ား ႏိူင္ငံေရး သမားေဟာင္းမ်ား
ေထာင္က်မွာ မေၾကာက္သူမ်ားကို ဦးေဆာင္မႈေနရာေပးခဲ့ၾကတယ္ ။
ေတာ္လွန္ေရး နယ္ေျမေရာက္သြားတဲ့ သူေတြက
လက္ကိုင္ကိုင္ တိုက္ပြဲေတြနဲ ့ၾကိဳးပန္းခဲ့ၾကတယ္ ။
ျပည္တြင္းက ဦးေဆာင္ခဲ့သူမ်ား တပ္အေၾကာင္းေလ့လာသူမ်ား
အဂၤလိပ္စကား စာတတ္သူမ်ား
အမ်ားစု ၾကိဳက္တဲ့သူ ။ ေသမွာ မေၾကာက္တဲ့ သူေတြကို
ဦေဆာင္မႈေနရာေပးခဲ့ၾကတယ္ ။
ထိုင္းႏိုင္ငံေရာက္သြားသူေတြက သတင္းျဖန္ ့ခ်ီေရး ဆႏၵျပသမႈေတြနဲ ့လႈပ္ရွားခဲ့ၾကတယ္ ။
ေက်ညာခ်က္ကို ကၽြမ္းကၽြမ္းက်င္က်င္ ေရးႏိုင္သူမ်ား ။
အခက္အခဲကို ဦးေဆာင္ႏိူင္သူမ်ား
လူစုႏိူင္သူမ်ားကို ဦးေဆာင္မႈေနရာေပးခဲ့ၾကတယ္
အႏွစ္ ၂၀ ေက်ာ္သြားေတာ့ ၾကိဳးပန္းမႈေတြရဲ ့ ရလဒ္ကို
အာဏာရွင္စစ္တပ္ကလူေတြ ခံစားတတ္လာျပီ ။
ေတာ္လွန္ေရး ကာလမွာ လက္ေတြ ့ပိုင္းအရ မွားခဲ့တာရွိတယ္ ။
ျမန္မာျပည္ အာဏာရွင္ ျဖဳတ္ခ်ေရးအတြက္ေတာ့ တခါမွ မမွားၾကေသးဖူး ။
စစ္အာဏာရွင္ေတြက သူတို ့သားစဥ္ေျမးဆက္ ခ်မ္းသာ ၾကြယ္ဝစြာ လံုျခံဳေရးအတြက္
ျမန္ဆန္လွနဲ ့ နည္းေတြနဲ ့ ျမန္မာျပည္ကို ေျပာင္းလဲေနျပီ ။
သားစဥ္ေျမးဆက္ လံုျခံဳဖို ့ တိုင္းျပည္ကို အုပ္ခ်ဳပ္တဲ့ နည္းစနစ္ကေတာ့
လူအမ်ား ဆႏၵနဲ့ သေဘာထားေတြကို အေကာင္အထည္ေဖၚတဲ့
ေရြးေကာက္ပြဲ ကလာတဲ့ လူထုကိုယ္စားလွယ္ေတြနဲ ့ လြတ္ေတာ္ တည္ေဆာက္ျပီ း
ဒီမိုကေရစီ စနစ္က်င့္သံုးဖို ့ျဖစ္တယ္ ။
ဦးသုေဝ ေျပာခဲ့သလို စစ္တပ္က ေျခတလွမ္း ေနာက္ဆုတ္ေနပါတယ္ ။
ဘယ္သူ ့အတြက္လဲ ။ ဘယ္နည္းလက္ေတြ နဲ ့တိုင္းျပည္နဲ ့လူမ်ိဳးေတြ အတြက္ အသံုးခ်မလဲ ။
အႏွစ္ ၂၀ ေက်ာ္ တိုက္ပြဲ အသြင္ပံုစံ ေျပာင္းလာခဲ့ျပီ ။
နည္းမ်ိဳးစံုနဲ ့ ခ်မယ္ ဆိုတာနဲ ့ အသံက်ယ္က်ယ္ ေအာ္ျပီး
ေခါင္းေဆာင္ေနရာ မွာေနလို ့မရေတာ့ဖူး ။
လြတ္ေတာ္ထဲမွ တဆင့္ က်ယ္ျပန္ ့လာေနတဲ ့ အာဏာရွင္ စစ္မ်က္ႏွာကို
တိုက္ခိုက္ေျပာင္းလဲဖို ့ စစ္မ်က္ႏွာ ၃ မ်ိဳးဖြင့္ရေတာ့မယ္ ။
တရားဝင္ ပါတီ ထူေထာင္ျခင္း
လူထု လူတန္းစား အသီးသီး အသိပညာေပး အဖြဲ ့ အုပ္စုမ်ားထူေထာင္ျခင္း
ႏိူင္ငံတကာေရာက္ ျမန္မာႏိူင္ငံသား အဖြဲ ့မ်ား ထူေထာင္ျခင္း
ကၽြန္ေတာ္တို ့ ဦးေဆာင္ေနသူေတြကို မွန္မွန္ကန္ကန္ ေရြးခ်ယ္ေပးဖို ့လိုေနပါျပီ ။
ဥိးေဆာင္ေနသူေတြရဲ ့ အရည္အခ်င္းကို ဆန္းစစ္ဖို ့လိုေနပါျပီ ။
အနာဂါတ္ ျမန္မာျပည္အတြက္ ကၽြမ္းက်င္သူေတြေမြးထုတ္ဖို ့လိုလာပါျပီ ။
လက္ရွိ ေျပာင္းလဲျခင္း တိုက္ပြဲေတြအတြက္
ဘာသာရပ္ကၽြမ္းက်င္သူေတြနဲ ့ပူးေပါင္းဦးေဆာင္ႏိူင္ဖို ့လိုလာပါျပီ ။
ကၽြန္ေတာ္တို ့ ေခါင္းေဆာင္ေဟာင္းေတြ ျပင္ဆင္ေနၾကျပီလား ။
ကၽြန္ေတာ္တို ့ေခါင္းေဆာင္သစ္ေတြ ရွာေဖြပီးၾကျပီလား ။
အေျပာင္းအလဲ လိုေနျပီ ဆိုလား
(မွတ္ခ်က္ )
ျပည္ပေရာက္
အဖြဲ ့အစည္းေတြက ဦးေဆာင္ေနသူ အခ်ိဳ ့ကေျပာၾကတယ္ ။ အေမစု လြတ္လာျပီ ။ သူ
့ရဲ ့ဦးေဆာင္မႈေနာက္က လိုက္ၾကမယ္တဲ့ ။ ၁၀၀ % လက္ခံတယ္ ။ အေမစုနဲ ့ NLD ကို
လက္ေတြ ့ပံ့ပိုးဖို ့ ဆက္လက္ျပီး ေရာက္ရွိေနတဲ့ နယ္ပယ္ အသီးသီးမွာ
ျပင္ဆင္ရေတာ့မယ္ ။ အေမစု လြတ္ေျမာက္ေရး
မင္းကိုႏိူင္နဲ ့၈၈ ေက်ာင္းသားေတြ လြတ္ေျမာက္ေရး ႏိူင္ငံေရ အက်ဥ္းသားေတြ
လြတ္ေျမာက္ေရး အတြက္ ဖြဲ ့စည္းခဲ့တဲ့ ျပည္ပအဖြဲ ့အစည္းေတြ
အေျပာင္းအလဲလိုေနျပီ ။ အသံက်ယ္တဲ့ လူေတြ ေခါင္းေဆာင္ဖို ့ထက္ ။
အရည္အခ်င္းရွိတဲ့ သူေတြကို ရွာေဖြျပီး ပူးေပါင္းႏိုင္ဖို ့လိုတယ္ ။ ၈၈ေတြက
လူငယ္ေတြကို ရွာေဖြ လက္တြဲျပီး ေန႕ရာေပးရေတာ့မယ္လို ့ျမင္လို ့ပါ ။
ကၽြန္ေတာ္ေရးတာ စကားလံုးေတြ
လိုသြားတယ္ ။ ၈၈ေတြက လူငယ္ေတြ ဆိုတာက ၈၈ ေက်ာင္းသားေတြက လူငယ္သစ္
မ်ိဳးဆက္သစ္ေတြ ရွာေဖြဖို ့ပါ ။ ၁၉၈၈ ဦးေဆာင္ခဲ့သူေတြက အခု အခ်ိန္မ်ာ
အသက္အရြယ္အားျဖင့္ ၄၅ ေက်ာ္လာၾကျပီ ။ ေနာက္ထပ္လုပ္ႏိူင္ၾကရင္ ၁၅ ႏွစ္ေပါ့ ။
ႏိူင္ငံတခုကို ဦးေဆာင္ထို ့လူငယ္ေတြကို
ေမြးထုတ္ထို ့ဆိုတာ ႏွစ္ေတြ အမ်ားၾကီး အေတြ ့အၾကံဳရဖို ့လိုပါတယ္။လက္ရွိ
အေမစုက ၆၅ ႏွစ္ ။ သူျပီးရင္ ၄၅ ၅၀ အရြယ္ေတြကို လက္ဆင့္ကမ္းရေတာ့မယ္ ။ ေနာက္
၁၅ ႏွစ္ မွာ ျမန္မာျပည္ကို ၁၀၀ % ျပည့္ ဒီမိုကေရစီ ႏိူင္ငံျဖစ္ဖို ့ပါ ။
စစ္တကၠသိုလ္ၾကီးက တိုက္ခိုက္ေရး ေခါင္းေဆာင္ေတြ ႏွစ္စဥ္ စနစ္တက်
ေမြးထုတ္ေပးေနတယ္ ။ သူတို ့က အုပ္စု အားေကာင္းေတာ့ ဒီကေန ့ တိုင္းျပည္
အုပ္ခ်ဳပ္ေရးကို သူတို ့ေနရာယူထားတယ္ ။ ကၽြန္ေတာ္တို ့ မျပင္ဆင္ရင္ ေနာက္
အႏွစ္ ၂၀ က်ရင္လဲ သူတို ့စစ္တပ္က လာတဲ့သူ တင္တဲ့ သူဘဲ အုပ္ခ်ဳပ္ေနၾကမွာ ။
ASHGATE
RESEARCH
COMPANION 1
Political Leadership in Context
Joseph Masciulli, Mikhail A.
Molchanov and W. Andy Knight
Research in political science
is mostly problem-driven (George and Bennett 2005;
see Shapiro 2007, who
convincingly opposes a method-driven approach). Among
the many issues that political
science deals with, the problem of leadership clearly
stands out. Leadership is an
essential feature of all government and governance: weak
leadership contributes to
government failures, and strong leadership is indispensable
if the government is to
succeed. Wise leadership secures prosperity in the long run;
foolhardy leadership may bring
about a catastrophe. The lack of leadership routinizes
governance. Its political and
creative aspects fade away: it becomes no different from
administration, focusing solely
on pattern maintenance and repetition of the same. On
the other hand, over-assertive
leadership pays little attention to institutional constraints:
it may bring about sudden,
unexpected changes, and disrupt the normal flow of the
political process, thus
detracting from its transparency and/or predictability.
Political leadership and
followership account for significant differences across
and within individual nation
states in responding to both newer global problems
and traditional governance
issues. Globalization creates the demand for new forms
of international and
supranational leadership: as a ‘package of transnational flows
of people, production,
investment, information, ideas, and authority’ (Brysk 2002,
1; cf. Masciulli and Day 2006),
globalization elevates the significance of leadership
of international organizations,
regional groups of states, and global agencies
(Masciulli and Day 2006; Keck
and Sikkink 1998).
Leadership is a historically
concrete phenomenon; that is, its structures and
methods change with the passage
of time. To influence events and affect outcomes,
leaders need to be prepared to
abandon policy instruments and ideas that no longer
work in a new environment. They
need to be able to embrace the new and reevaluate
the old, even some of the
earlier discarded ideas and methods of adapting
to environments, if the
circumstances call for it. Contributors to this book attempt to
demonstrate in various ways
that strategic-tactical innovative adaptation is the key
to effective political
leadership in a diverse set of regime types and cultural contexts.
Innovations may take different
forms, however. Though all of our authors are generally
committed to democracy, human
rights and environmental sustainability, we do not
entirely agree on what these
ideals mean theoretically and imply practically.
The Ashgate Research Companion
to Political Leadership
Definitions
In this research companion, we
investigate political leadership as a multidimensional
phenomenon. Leadership is a
part of multicausal social processes that bring about
concrete political outcomes –
election results, for example (King 2002; Greenstein
2004). In the literature on
leadership and management, political leadership from
the local to the national to
the global level is usually and correctly viewed as a
subtype of human social
leadership – though we would stress that it is a special
‘thick’, potentially
all-inclusive, subtype. To understand, explain and predict
patterns of political
leadership and arrive at normative prescriptions for its
‘proper’ design and
implementation, inquirers need to analyse the beliefs, values,
characters, power relations,
and ethical/unethical values, attitudes and actions of
leaders and followers, as well
as their historical situation and cultural-institutional
context (Nye 2008). Both
leaders and followers are involved in a circular process
of motivation and power
exchange that is often difficult to break up into a causal
sequence (Wildavsky 2006).
Still ‘politics as leadership’ (Tucker 1995) does occur,
however complex it is to
conclude about the significance of its causal role: leaders
mobilize a significant number
of followers to accept their diagnosis of, and policy
prescriptions for, collective
problems or crises. Moreover, leadership is a symbolic
activity mediated by culture,
for leaders as ‘identity entrepreneurs’ are engaged in
providing myths/visions to
create, reshape or enhance national and other political
cultures. In the process,
leaders and followers themselves are affected by what they
help create (Rousseau 1987; The
Social Contract, II, 7).
Political leadership is one of
the most widely experienced and intuitively or tacitly
understood phenomena – like
great power competition, Olympic rivalries, climate
change, the right to develop,
or central human rights controversies about trade-offs
between security and civil and
political rights. In contrast, the concept of political
leadership is difficult to
define essentially, because
it is dependent on institutional,
cultural and historical
contexts and situations – both particular and general (Blondel
1987; Wildavsky 2006; Wildavsky
1989; Klenke 1996). Empirical operationalization
of the concept of leadership
involves a host of methodological issues, specifically
those related to the definition
of variables and the problem of spurious correlation.
Nonetheless, the phenomenon of
leadership clearly incorporates leaders involved
in some type of innovative
adaptation with followers, group objectives and
organizational means, and
problematic situations and contexts (Drucker with
Maciariello 2008; Nye 2008;
Grint 2005).
The Concise Oxford English
Dictionary defines a ‘leader’ as ‘the person who
leads or commands a group,
organization, or country’. ‘To lead’ means to ‘cause
(a person or animal) to go with
one by drawing them along; show (someone) the
way to a destination by
preceding or accompanying them’. In other words, goalsetting
and motivation both figure
prominently as essential attributes of the notion
of leadership. Other languages
differ considerably with the meanings of equivalent
translatable terms, but have
also adopted the English ‘leader’ and ‘leadership’ in
the last century (Blondel
1987).
Political Leadership in
Context
‘Leadership’ is of more recent
usage. The term was coined in the early nineteenth
century and refers to
the dignity, office, or
position of a leader, esp. of a political party; ability to
lead; the position of a group
of people leading or influencing others within
a given context; the group
itself; the action or influence necessary for the
direction or organization of
effort in a group undertaking (Oxford English
Dictionary,
online).
One should note that military
command has been and remains a standard dictionary
meaning of leadership in the
Oxford English Dictionary and other English dictionaries
(other languages present their
own linguistic diversity and complexity because of
historical and cultural
differences). In the military, people in positions of command
show followers the way, but are
not open to debates in which the force of the better
argument decides the course of
action (cf. Habermas 1971). Their hard power of
command with coercive
enforcement is always in reserve to ‘guide’ the followers in
the direction chosen by the leaders.
Indeed, the ancient linguistic root of the English
verb ‘to lead’ means ‘to go
forth, die’ (American Heritage Dictionary 1969,
1526).
As regards an overall guiding
definition of political leadership for research
purposes, cultural context
matters in giving substantial content to any definition. For
example, in a Russian cultural
context, a leader with a sentimental, compassionate
or weak character would be
rejected as a failure (Gorbachev’s weakness versus
Putin’s strength as contrasting
images) (Wildavsky 2006; House et al. 2004).
Moreover, research purposes do
allow for a plurality of definitions, each of which
is appropriate to the type of
study undertaken (Bass 1990). Still, most researchers
agree that the following
elements should be taken into account in defining political
leadership:
the personality and traits of a
leader or leaders, including her or his ethical
and cultural character;
the traits and ethical-cultural
character of the followers with whom the leader
interacts (keeping in mind that
leaders of different followers and followers of
different leaders interact as
well, cooperatively or competitively);
the societal or organizational
context in which the leader–follower interaction
occurs – general culture,
political culture, political climate, norms, and
institutions;
the agenda of collective
problems or tasks which confront the leaders and
followers in particular
historical situations;
the nature of the leader’s
interpretive judgement, since situations do not
define themselves, but have to
be defined by leaders’ insights accepted by
the followers;
the means – material and
intangible – that the leaders use to attain their ends
and/or their followers’ goals;
these are ‘the techniques which the leader uses
to mobilize support on behalf
of her or his agenda and/or to maintain support
or position’ (Peele 2005, 192);
•
•
•
•
•
•
The Ashgate Research Companion
to Political Leadership
the effects or results of
leadership (whether real or symbolic, long lasting or
transient).
‘Political leadership’ overlaps
significantly with the higher levels of military, legal,
organizational, and religious
and ideological leadership, and is a special part of
‘social leadership’ in general,
as we contended above. The latter includes parental,
business, educational,
scientific and technological, athletic, medical, cultural,
artistic, religious, and other
forms of leadership. Some scholars focus on social
leadership as a whole, and deal
with political leadership as a part among parts
(such as Grint 2000; Grint
2005). Social leadership and political leadership manifest
themselves in formal positions
and behaviourally. Scholars who stress that political
leadership is a special part of
social leadership also affirm that leadership is ‘related
to power: a leader (in the behavioral
sense) is a person who is able to modify the
course of events’ (Blondel
1987; Wildavsky 2006).
One notes that power and
leadership are equally elusive concepts that are both
difficult to operationalize.
The alternative is to go in the direction of strict stipulative
definitions, but this may
present us with research dilemmas and methodological
issues beyond the scope of this
book. We agree with those who define political
leadership as a rather unique
set of power relations and influences that is exercised
over a broad range of
nationally and globally salient issue areas and from a position
of authoritative preponderance
involving ideologies and ethics:
While many of us have power
over a group, perhaps for relatively long periods,
and may be [social] leaders as
a result, political leaders exercise this power
over an area comprising
foreign affairs, defense, the economic and social wellbeing
of citizens, even culture and
the arts. … [Indeed,] at least in principle,
political leadership is broad
and might be all-embracing: decisions that could
be taken by the [political]
leader might cover any subject (Blondel 1987, 15).
There is an overlap between
social and political leadership, but the latter is ‘thicker’
than any other type of social
leadership in having a monopolistic or preferred
access to coercive and inducing
hard power, in addition to attracting, persuasive
soft power based on ideology,
symbolism, ethical/non-ethical character, and
perceptions of followers about
leaders.
Analytical Framework
Political leadership implies
followership, as well as group tasks to be accomplished
through innovative adaptation
in a specific situation and institutionalcultural
context (Heifetz 1994; Tucker
1995; Nye 1999; Bennis and Thomas
2002; Nye 2008). Leadership–followership
is part of the social reality of any
group confronting its
environment as problematic, in which the group must
continually adapt and innovate.
The leadership–followership exchanges evolve
•
Political Leadership in
Context
into a real interactive
process, in which the two parts are mutually constitutive and
‘dialectically’ related as a
whole that is greater than the sum of the parts. Leaders
affect their followers’
attitudes, beliefs, demands and needs; and the followers
affect the leader’s style,
qualities, beliefs and motivations, as they both transform
the environment and are
reflectively transformed by their own actions (Blondel
1987, 17; Hay 2002; Tucker
1977a; Tucker 1981; Wildavsky 2006; Rousseau 1987, The
Social Contract, II, 7).
Whatever contextual variations
exist, political leadership–followership is always
a social process of adaptation
and innovation – hence, innovative adaptation – to
an environment or context that
challenges a group’s way of life and values. The
leader’s tasks are to:
interpret problems
prescribe ends and means to
solve them
propagate personal visions as
solutions or, at least, responses to problems
mobilize followers to implement
those solutions or responses (Heifetz 1994;
Tucker 1995).
A growing number of political analysts
see leadership as a dynamic, open social
system, a coherent process,
rather than just a number of sporadic individual acts:
‘some kind of process … that in
some way gets people to do something’, or involves
‘some sort of relationship
between leaders and followers in which something
happens or gets done’ (Ciulla
1998, 11–13; Burns 1978).
A leader, says Kellerman,
‘chooses a particular course of action and then in
some way gets others to go
along; or more subtly, the leader encourages the led to
‘choose’ the course that the
group will follow …’ (2004, xiii). The co-determination
of the two parts of the
leadership–followership system means that leaders are, to a
significant extent, created by
the led. Followers matter; indeed ‘leadership, seen as
a process, is caused by
following’ (Mant 1999, 6). Whether people follow primarily
by inner ‘instinct’ (Mant 1999)
or through cultural socialization (both obviously
are involved), the significance
of followership for leaders’ successes and failures
has become better appreciated
in the recent literature (Hollander 1998; Kellerman
2008).
The actual ‘supply’ of
leadership is driven by a pre-existing societal ‘demand’,
which the political
entrepreneurship of a would-be leader seeks to satisfy. More
often than not, there is more
than one way to satisfy that demand, or to create an
impression that the problem can
be resolved. Historical contexts and problematic
situations are variously
‘interpreted’ by opposing elite groups, political leaders
themselves as members of these
elites, their advisers and organizational ‘machines’,
and mass followers (Michels
1986). Political leadership may therefore be seen as a
form of competitive
entrepreneurial activity in the marketplace of ideas and values,
sometimes stressing structural
leadership, intellectual leadership or charismatic
leadership (Young 1991). Of
course, in addition to leadership–followership, elite–
mass formations, alienated
apolitical individuals, independent intellectuals, and
professional and epistemic
communities are also involved in interpreting their
••••
The Ashgate Research Companion
to Political Leadership
common world and its problems
(Tucker 1977a; Tucker 1981; Tucker 1995; Keck
and Sikkink 1998; Scott 2001).
However, leader–follower groups are unique, as
they not only interpret
problematic situations, but also prescribe specific courses
of action and mobilize people
to solve social problems, thus seeking to transform
existing contexts and
situations (Tucker 1995).
It is important to stress that
contextual and situational interpretations are
not ‘pre-programmed’ into the
fabric of social life. As environments are not selfdefining
or obvious to political actors,
a conscious interpretive effort is called forth
and provided by political
leaders. The results of such an effort are naturally open
to political and ideological
contestation (Stier 1997). Social environments are not
reducible to natural or
technological entities that are simply ‘out there’ for all to
see, but rather also include
socially constructed facts resulting from the norms and
practices accepted by a group
(Ruggie 1998). To be sure, some contexts are relatively
easier to interpret than others
– for example, famines, natural disasters, military
invasions, disease pandemics
and severe economic recessions or depressions – such
as the deep global recession
that started in 2008. Even so, once cause-and-effect
relationships enter into
political discourse, once responsibility gets assigned and
accountability demanded, the
re-interpretive function of leadership immediately
comes to the fore, and the
space for political entrepreneurship and creativity
increases exponentially
(Guntern 1997).
While traditional studies saw
great leaders as creative agents driving political
processes for the society at
large (Carlyle 1993; Hook 1943), newer research is
placing increased emphasis on
the necessity to avoid drawing a simple dichotomy
between social structures and
political agency, including leader–follower groups.
Social structures are
‘collections of people, organized perhaps in some ‘system’ or
multiple systems, but still
people, and thus malleable, susceptible to the ultimate
agency of human learning and
leadership (Burns 2003, 216). In other words, unlike
natural structures, social
structures are only relatively enduring and do not exist
independently of the activities
they regulate or constitute (Hay 2002; Ruggie 1998).
Agents who accept shared
conceptions, norms and identities in their activities
construct social structures
that persist only as long as these conceptions, norms and
identities remain relatively
static and do not significantly change. Some leader–
follower interactive groups are
long-lasting; others are temporary, contingent upon
the ‘strategic selectivity’ of
the group’s structural environment (Hay 1995, 192; Hay
2002).
The leader–follower
relationship exists on a continuum from extreme inequality
and asymmetry, whereby strong
leaders exercise overwhelming domination
over subordinate followers (a
significant constant in the past and present), to the
opposite extreme of almost
total symmetry and equality, whereby strong leaders
influence and inspire followers
to become strong, autonomous leaders themselves
(a rare utopian event, except
within elite leadership circles involving leaders, coand
sub-leaders and advisers).
Leadership at both ends of the continuum, however,
is characterized by
interaction, whether it is materially ‘transactional’ or morally
‘transformational’ (Burns 1978;
Burns 2003).
Political Leadership in
Context
Moreover, one can distinguish
between ‘adaptive’ leaders who react and
respond to challenges from
local and global systems by introducing changes on
the margins, and ‘innovative’
leaders who seek to implement more radical changes
and revise the very rules of
the game, or the nature of societal responses to the
problem (Heifetz 1994).
Innovative leaders frequently demonstrate exceptional
(‘charismatic’) leadership
which seems to emanate from the personality of a
leader. Charismatic leadership
tends to arise in times of crisis and always leads,
for temporary periods at least,
away from the world of everyday life and everyday
routine (Takala 1997).
Innovative leadership, says Sheffer (1993), refers to:
… dominant leaders who
introduced new ideas or novel orientations, and for
better or for worse promoted
major changes in their respective societies, which
in turn altered both the
nearer and more remote external environments of these
societies … [by advancing]
vision, inspiration, conceptualization of change,
articulation of ideological goals
and their communication to followers and
foes, risk taking, [the]
formation of groups of followers and their occasional
mobilization, [and] guidance
of followers toward the achievement of goals
(vii–ix).
Sheffer’s summary refers to
‘fuzzy’ concepts such as vision, inspiration and risktaking.
These concepts seem to be of a
subjective nature and refer to individual
psychological qualities of a
leader. However, none of those qualities would be
of any interest to us, if not
for their lasting social importance. When a leader’s
‘charisma’, vision and
inspiration become the catalysts of social and political
change, they leave the realm of
individual psychology and acquire the new qualities
of an intersubjective reality
shared by a great number of people. It is these people’s
actions, guided by a common set
of goals first articulated by a leader or leaders,
that objectify the leader’s
vision and help transform the environment.
What is good leadership and how
does it differ from bad leadership? This is an
area where empirical political
science encounters normative political theory. The
terms are loaded. We tend to
believe that ‘good’ leadership should be good both
ethically and instrumentally
(cf. Ciulla 1998, 13). ‘Bad’ leadership can be designated
as such if it is morally evil,
rests on the violation of human dignity and rights (or
some variant moral
orientation), or caters solely to the egoistic whims and private
interests of a ruler. It may
also be ‘bad’ in the sense of being ineffective due to,
for example, incompetence,
rigidity or intemperance in leaders or followers that
interferes with the use of
appropriate means to attain the ends sought (Kellerman
2004).
In ‘effective’ leadership, the
leader successfully chooses the means that bring
about the desired ends. If the
means chosen are devised anew – rather than simply
taken from the arsenal of
time-tested, routine responses to typical problems –
effective leadership
corresponds to the pattern of innovative adaptation. Complex
leadership can be both
‘effective’ and ‘ethical’; that is, the leader successfully
chooses the means that are most
likely to attain the ends sought, but also seeks
to embody end-values (equality,
freedom, justice, human rights, environmental
The Ashgate Research Companion
to Political Leadership
10
sustainability) and
modal-values (honesty, reliability, trustworthiness, fairness) in
the process (Burns 1998,
ix–xii). The effectiveness of leadership is determined by
the actual short- and long-
term consequences of leaders’ actions. Judgement of
a leader’s effectiveness may be
revised in historiographies, in view of long-term
consequences.
The degree of ethics in
leadership is determined by relevant argumentation and
discourse (Ciulla 1998; Ciulla
2004a). However, there is a core set of ethical/moral
insights that is available for
practical application: principles of the just-war tradition
(Lauren et al. 2007; Walzer
1992); reciprocity (Kegley 1995b); elementary principles
of distributive justice
requiring that society or the dominant group care for the ill,
the most vulnerable, the
starving, and the economically worst-off (Rawls 1999;
Walzer 2007; Miller 2007;
Singer 2004); and an appreciation of the core virtues of
ethics including practical
wisdom and judgement, moderation, courage, and a sense
of fairness and justice,
sympathy and compassion (Coll 1995; Dalai Lama 1993).
Some theorists argue that
leadership by definition is ethically good (Northouse
2004). It is ‘a process whereby
an individual influences a group of individuals to
achieve a common goal’ but
without using coercion (Northouse 2004, 3; cf. Burns
1978). Kellerman (1999; 2004)
and Bass (1990; 1998; 1985) have correctly pointed
out that the Northouse-Burns
approach has a fundamental weakness, which is the
problem of the so-called ‘Hitler’s
ghost’. Kellerman argues that not only was Hitler’s
impact on the twentieth century
arguably greater than any other state leader’s; Hitler
was skilled at inspiring,
mobilizing and directing his followers. Notwithstanding
the indiscriminate use of coercion
against followers and adversaries alike, and
despite the evil of his racist
and Social Darwinist ends, Hitler’s leadership was
unusually effective in a purely
instrumental sense of the word (Kellerman 2004, 11).
Kellerman’s argument is
empirically persuasive. We cannot dismiss the problem of
instrumentally effective, even
if morally repugnant, leadership by simply refusing
to use the term ‘leader’ in
such cases. Labelling Hitler as a ‘ruler’, ‘tyrant’ or
‘power-wielder’ in pointed
avoidance of the term ‘leader’ (cf. Burns 1978) does little
service to empirical political
science. If we decide to limit the studied universe of
leaders by weeding out all
tyrants, egoistic ‘power-wielders’ and morally deficient
individuals, the remaining
number of cases might be too few from which to draw
any meaningful conclusions. For
comparative purposes, we would, therefore, seek
to employ a value-neutral
definition of leadership that focuses on its instrumental
(ability to influence people
and effect outcomes), organizational (goal-setting and
motivation),
strategic-visionary and entrepreneurial (innovative adaptation and
creativity) qualities, rather
than post hoc normative
evaluation of its end-results.
Successful leaders are those
who have demonstrated their ability to move
their society tangibly in the
direction that seemed clearly supportive of their
suggested ‘grand design’.
Unsuccessful leaders are those whose efforts to move
their society in the direction
of their choosing have backfired or brought about
results clearly destructive of
their propagated strategic vision. Historical evidence
suggests that a good number of
political leaders evade academic attempts at neat
classification, as they
switched from the one to the other side of the ‘successful/
unsuccessful’ divide at various
times in their political careers and especially in
Political Leadership in
Context
11
regards to this or that
particular element of a ‘grand design’ under consideration.
Without a doubt, the
‘successful/unsuccessful’ classification is also profoundly
influenced by the interpreter’s
point of view, methodological premises and
evaluative frames.
In the voluminous, and growing,
social science literature on political leadership
and followership, one can find
a variety of theoretical and methodological
approaches to studying
leadership, but little agreement on what reliable knowledge
about leadership does exist
(for example, Grint 1997; Grint 2000; Grint 2005;
Kellerman 2008; Peele 2005; Nye
2008; Yukl 2009). Defining, explaining, predicting
and evaluating leadership are
all areas of active scholarly debate. Nonetheless,
there is a degree of consensus
among political scientists and historians that the case
study approach with qualitative
methods, and the systematic use of counterfactual
analysis (Kellerman 2004;
Kellerman 2008; Gergen 2000; George and Bennett
2005; Greenstein 2004; Ferguson
1999), combined with comparative quantitative
investigations (for example,
King 2002; Rejai and Phillips 1983) have been and
will continue to be
indispensable for arriving at reliable knowledge about political
leadership – without denying
the value of experimental and other methods used to
study leadership in social and
political psychology (Lane 2003).
Given the importance of
impersonal cultural, ecological, demographic,
scientific-technological, and
institutional structures globally and within states,
what role do individual
political leaders actually play and how causally significant
are their contributions in
bringing about political outcomes? The debate about
whether particular leaders with
their personal attributes, characters, beliefs,
values and skills should be
considered as important historical, causal agents in
their own right remains at the
centre stage of leadership studies (King 2002; Post
2004). Do leaders change
history, or do historical forces primarily move them? Why
do followers follow leaders –
because of leaders’ ‘charisma’ or, less mysteriously,
because of tangible economic or
other self-interests of followers? What part of a
leader’s world-historical
personality might be regarded as properly individual
and personal, and what part of
it as a mere reflection of the predominant social
structures and historical
situations?
We suggest that individual
leadership approaches in conjunction with contextual
and situational approaches are
indispensable for understanding causality in
international relations and
comparative politics today. Leadership studies provide
a productive source for
hypotheses that seek to clarify the agency-structure nexus
across the broad spectrum of
social and political sciences. In addition, these studies
help formulate prescriptive
positions for solving national and global problems,
some of which arise from the
lack of effective individual leadership, while some
others reflect individual
leaders’ miscalculations or plain inadequacy (Byman
and
Pollack 2001; Greenstein 1982; Greenstein 2004; Lauren et al. 2007; George
and George 1998). As the debate
continues, there are also those who opt for the
primacy of social structures
and reject the usefulness of theorizing at the level of
the actions and personalities
of individual leaders (for example, Waltz 1959; Waltz
1979; Mearsheimer 2001).
The Ashgate Research Companion
to Political Leadership
12
The personality-centred
approach is advanced by studies of some highly
effective political leaders who
have themselves ‘consciously developed theories
of leadership that functioned
with compelling success in their own worlds’: for
example, Franklin D. Roosevelt
and Stanley Baldwin (Hamby 2006, 233); Churchill
(Lord 2003); Lenin (Service
2000); Deng Xiaoping (Shambaugh 1995); and even
such socially destructive and
narcissistic leaders as Mao, Stalin and Hitler (Tucker
1987, 34–40, 199). US President
Dwight D. Eisenhower (1953–61) has been described
by Greenstein (1988, 105) as a
‘leadership theorist in the White House’, one who
‘drew extensively on an
explicit conception of the means and ends of leadership
that he had developed before
assuming office’. Studying the letters, memoirs
and polemical writings of
successful leadership ‘practitioners’ and innovators as
different as Mahatma Gandhi,
Martin Luther King, Jr. and Nelson Mandela, on
the one hand, and Kemal
Ataturk, Vladimir Lenin and Fidel Castro, on the other
hand, might provide glimpses
into their respective leadership approaches and
strategies, thus helping to
advance theoretical conceptualizations and sound
practical prescriptions.
Nonetheless, sceptics argue
that the prominence and influence of individual,
personal leadership is
overstated in the press and in scholarly case studies. To the
critics of a leadership-focused
approach in political science, ‘it is not at all clear
that leadership requires any
remarkable talents, or that major differences in the
success of organizations
reflect differences in the capabilities of their leaders, or
that history is the product of
leaders’ actions’ (March and Weil 2005, 97). Citing such
evidence as King’s (2002)
quantitative study of the relation of leaders’ personalities
to election outcomes in six
countries, some scholars conclude that, in view of the
study’s uneven results, the
judgments, decisions and actions of leaders in modern
democratic societies do not
matter much (Grint 2005). However, King contends that
despite particular national
elections not being a leaders’ ‘beauty contest’, leaders
always matter in developing
party platforms before and during elections, pursuing
electoral strategies, and later
governing with one leadership style or another. We
agree with King (2002) that
both the leadership approach and the organizational
and impersonal forces’ approach
are needed to understand and explain political
outcomes and develop policies.
The Marxist tradition of
political leadership is valuable for its insights into
agency-structure dynamics under
conditions of reform or revolution (Marsh 2002).
Marxist-inspired political
theorists of leadership have had to respond to Marx’s
heavy emphasis on structural
economic and technological forces advancing class
conflict to the point of a
revolutionary political and cultural transformation of
society in the direction of
socialism and communism, which he saw as the final
stage of political-economic
development. To be sure, Marx qualified his seeming
structural determinism with the
notion of mutual dialectical transformation of
individual and collective
agents and the historical situation and contexts (Marsh
2002). Friedrich Engels and
subsequent Marxist theorists went further than
that, emphasizing the role of
‘ideological relations’ and other ‘superstructural’
phenomena in the maintenance
and adaptation of modern capitalist relations of
production and social control
(for example, Gramsci 1971).
Political Leadership in
Context
13
In the subsequent
Marxist-Leninist tradition, leadership is understood as a
function to be performed by a
group of committed individuals – a party, or an
organization of professional
revolutionaries – vested with the role of ‘lending
energy, stability, and
continuity to the political struggle’ of the working class (Lenin
1975, 63). Several important
features distinguish Lenin’s approach to leadership,
including the unabashed
emphasis on the superior qualities of the leadership elite.
First of all, the leadership
elite of a movement must claim a superior knowledge
or understanding of not only
the long-term goals and immediate tasks of the
movement, but of the society at
large and the laws of history that govern its
evolution. The mastery of
revolutionary theory is the surest way to the mastery
of a revolutionary movement, as
‘the role of
vanguard fighter can be fulfilled only by a
party that is guided by the
most advanced theory’ (Lenin 1975, 19–20).
Second, Lenin conceives of
leadership as a collective, rather than individual
function and attribute,
although the leading elite is by no means seen as inclusive,
broad-based, or numerous: ‘…
without the “dozen” tried and talented leaders
(and talented men are not born
by the hundreds) … working in perfect harmony,
no class in modern society can
wage a determined struggle’ (Lenin 1975, 74). The
elite’s primary task is to
educate the followers, to shape their understanding of
their own interests and the
world outlook generally speaking: ‘Class political
consciousness can be brought to
workers only from without …’ (Lenin 1975, 50). The
‘wise men’ that instil the
right type of consciousness into the masses of followers
could be of any class
background – ‘students or working men’ – as long as they are
‘professional revolutionaries’ (Lenin
1975, 76). The latter term implies a combination
of unique personal qualities,
stringent training and a lifetime of devotion to their
political leadership
(‘revolutionary’) career. Third, the leadership elite is supposed
to employ superior knowledge
and expert skills to organize followership: political
leaders are seen as ‘talented
organizers capable of arranging extensive and at the
same time uniform and
harmonious work that would employ all forces, even the
most inconsiderable’ (Lenin
1975, 80).
There is a consistent emphasis
on an objective, inescapable contradiction
between the ‘spontaneity of the
masses’ and ‘a high degree of consciousness’ that
should distinguish ‘a constant
and continuous organization capable of leading the
whole movement’ (Lenin 1975,
32–3).
The whole body of Lenin’s work
on the question looks as if it were more informed
by neo-Hegelian thought on the
power of ideas, rather than classic materialist
determinism characteristic of
Marx. Indeed, Lenin’s Conspectus of Hegel’s Science
of Logic (2007) has
this remarkable admission: ‘The thought of the ideal passing
into the real is profound: very
important for history. But also in the personal life
of man it is clear that this
contains much truth. Against vulgar materialism. NB.
The difference of the ideal
from the material is also not unconditional …’ The
barely hidden idealism of
Lenin’s theory of leadership is premised on the notion of
superiority of theoretical
insight provided by Marxist scholarship. This theory of
leadership makes full excuse of
social experimentation, and proudly presents the
grand designs devised by the
few ‘wise men’ as not only the latest achievement of
The Ashgate Research Companion
to Political Leadership
14
social sciences, but as the
only correct insight into the objectively predetermined
path of social evolution that
the rest of humanity must follow.
Critical theorists have learned
much from the Marxist tradition, but have
proceeded in a variety of
directions, some trying to combine strong democracy with
strong leadership (Stier 1997).
Habermas and the Frankfurt School have proposed
three conceptions of political
activity in the context of the relationship of theory
to practice and leaders to
followers: the interpretive conception (the explication
of meanings since humans are
intentional and meaningful in their actions); the
technical conception
(using knowledge as a tool to change the social and natural
worlds through our
understanding of causal nexuses and other regularities); and
the educative conception
(enlightening people about which means are effective for
the ends that they desire to
pursue, as well as clarifying alternative ends available
for adoption) (Stier 1997, 116;
cf. Habermas 1971). These three forms of political
activity are often intertwined
in forms of political leadership, though clearly ‘the
technical and educative uses of
political and social science are dependent on the
interpretive [theoretical] use’
(Stier 1997, 116). It is not clear, however, whether the
technical and educative uses of
knowledge and leadership can be reconciled, so
as to give priority to the
educative use in the pursuit of constitutional democracy,
human rights and environmental
sustainability. The constructive ordering of these
forms of political activity for
idealist-realist (not utopian) democratic, human
rights, and sustainability
leaders and followers would be the technical form
serving the educative form of
leadership, and both being informed by a strong
normative interpretation of
democracy as participative, human rights as implying
responsibilities, and
environmental sustainability including high-technology
innovation and adaptation.
Nonetheless, at times technical action would seem to
be needed to safeguard the
preservation of these educative ideals. There is no neat
Leninist resolution to these
dilemmas.
Typologies of Political Leadership
Typologies help us pose and
answer questions about leaders, followers, objectives,
situations and contexts.
Typologies are logical devices for the mental ordering of the
universe of cases. As
instruments of classification and ordering, typologies can be
used to describe various
observable groups of leaders and followers, the nature of
the relationship that binds the
two groups together, their social and psychological
traits, functions and social
roles, as well as the extent and character of the impact
they may have on a society at
large. Some of the pertinent questions that arise in
this regard are:
How and why do particular
individuals gain power in a particular
organization or society or
state? What are the origins of a leader’s power?
What are the instruments by
which this power is exercised (Blondel 1987)?
•
Political Leadership in
Context
15
How do and should leaders
exercise mixes of ‘hard’ and ‘soft’ power – that is,
‘smart power’ (Nye 2008)?
What are leaders’ and
followers’ personal characteristics (Greenstein 2004;
Hollander 1998; Kellerman
2008)? How do leaders and followers relate
(Kellerman 2004; Kellerman
2008; Burns 1978; Burns 2003)?
What functions do leaders serve
in what situations and contexts? How do they
diagnose problems, prescribe solutions,
and mobilize followers to implement
policies and visions (Tucker
1981; Tucker 1995)?
How do leaders and followers
realize their ‘vision’ (Bennis 2003; Greenstein
2004)?
What motivates leaders and
followers, and how do leaders motivate followers
and followers motivate leaders
(Lane 2003)?
Are there any types of leaders
not included in traditional, rational/pragmatic
and charismatic types (Weber
1946/1958)?
How do leaders move history or
does history move them (Hay 2002)?
Is there a type of leadership
‘for all seasons’ (Kellerman 1986; Nye 2008)?
Should ‘followers’ be abolished
as a term and reality or replaced by the term
and reality of ‘collaborators’
(Heifetz 1994; Shriberg et al. 2005)?
(Compare the lists of questions
in Heifetz 1994, 16, and Kellerman 1986, xiv.)
We know that all leadership
occurs in social situations and contexts, which
endow followers with certain
cultural characteristics, and which permit leaders to
utilize certain personal
characteristics: inherent qualities, socialized habits, learned
skills; intelligence of various
types, including especially emotional intelligence
and contextual intelligence,
including social insight; but also power-wielding,
organizational and
communication skills (cf. Greenstein 2004; Greenstein 2006;
Bose 2006; Nye 2008). We also
know that some leaders have ethical-political
visions, or at least some ideas
about what should be done for the group and in the
group (Bennis 2003; Bennis and
Biederman 1997). We know that leaders fulfil the
functions of diagnosing
problems, prescribing solutions and mobilizing followers
or supporters to solve those
problems and engage in change or preservation
through degrees of innovative
adaptation (Tucker 1981; Tucker 1995). Based on
this accumulated empirical and
analytical knowledge and normative perspectives,
researchers proceed with
constructing various kinds of typologies that usually
connect two or more variables
together; for example, leadership style and social
functions, or leader’s goals
and leadership outcomes.
Dichotomous typologies can be
constructed in relation to leaders’ individual
qualities and how they
generally relate to their followers and others – good or bad
(Kellerman 2004; Aristotle
1958), effective or ineffective (Greenstein 2004), strong
or weak (Deutsch 1978), formal
(constituted) versus informal (non-constituted)
leaders (Tucker 1981; Tucker
1995). Trichotomous typologies, especially during
the Cold War, stressed
differences among pragmatic (Western democratic, first
world), ideological (Communist,
second world) and revolutionary (independent
third world states) leaders
(Kissinger 1974). There are also normative and empirical
typologies, as well as those of
a mixed or hybrid nature.
•
•
•
•
•
•••
The Ashgate Research Companion
to Political Leadership
16
Normative Typologies
Normative typologies equip us
with an important instrument for ethical assessment
of leadership in the modern
world. Among the classic leadership typologies
still current in the West (but
see Lord, 2003, on Japan as a kind of ‘leaderless’
regime) one of the more popular
is Aristotle’s normative dualistic typology that
distinguishes between
self-interested rulers and leaders and common-interested
rulers and leaders. Aristotle’s
ethical thrust has been followed by many political
philosophers and empirical
theorists over the centuries. The tradition continues
today. Nye, for example, has
given his own version of a normative typology of
good and bad leadership.
Aristotle’s normative typology
of political leadership correlates two variables:
the number of rulers, on the
one hand, and the motivation and end results of their
ruling, on the other hand.
Thus, when one person rules for the common advantage,
the regime is a kingship;
one-person rule for private advantage results in a tyranny.
When a few rule for the common
advantage, the regime is an aristocracy; rule for
the particular gain of the few
results in an oligarchy. When the multitude rules for
the common good, the regime is
a polity (a constitutional democracy); rule for the
particular advantage of the
multitude (who, for the most part, are relatively poor),
results in an (electoral)
‘democracy’ or ‘mobocracy’ in today’s vocabulary (see Table
1.1; Aristotle 1958, 95–96,
119–20, 1279a20–25, 1289a25–35; Aristotle 1984).
While Aristotle tried to
distinguish between ‘good’ and ‘bad’ leadership based
on ideas that modern
scholarship summarizes under the notion of the public
interest, subsequent attempts
at normative theorizing paid more detailed attention
to the question of ‘good’
leadership and its specific characteristics. Nye’s modern
normative typology compares two
broadly accepted meanings of the term ‘good
leadership’: the one referring
to the leader’s ability to achieve results (whatever his
or her ends might be) and the
other offering an ethical judgement on the value of
the goals pursued, means
applied, and results obtained throughout the whole cycle
of leadership (see Table 1.2).
A clear-cut definition of the
foundations or premises of an ethical judgement
seems indispensable to make a normative
typology work in comparative contexts.
Thus, even ostensibly
‘value-free’ judgements of leadership effectiveness and
efficiency will have, upon
second thought, to be clarified against the foundational
Table 1.1 Good and Bad Regime
Leadership According to Aristotle
Number of rulers
End results and intention of
ruling
Common advantage or good
Private advantage or particular good
of the leader/s
One Kingship Tyranny
Few Aristocracy Oligarchy
Many Polity Democracy/Mobocracy
Source: Aristotle 1958.
Political Leadership in
Context
17
questions of the ‘good’ and
‘goodness’ and ‘right’ and ‘rightness’ when addressing
the ‘realism’ of the leader’s
ends, or the extent of the means-ends match, or, indeed,
the leader’s ability to
implement the group’s ‘true objectives’. Just as in the case of
Aristotle’s typology, defining
the ‘common advantage’ of the group, the group’s
‘interest’ as such, appears to
be the key. An even more complicated moral judgement
is called forth when the
group’s interest is scrutinized against any of the universal
moral criteria, which of
necessity engage considerations of the good of ‘others’, the
out-group reality and the
common values of humanity at large.
Empirical Typologies
Empirical typologies as an
approach refocuses the researcher’s attention on
the observable functions of
leadership, the personal qualities of a leader or the
sources of a leader’s
authority. Rather than assessing leadership from the sublime
perspective of terminal values,
empirical typologies seek to situate the problem
within a context of individual
and social psychology, group interactions and
intergroup processes, as
determined by historically concrete configurations of
social structures and
institutions. Max Weber’s tripartite ideal-type analytical
typology of traditional,
rational-legal and charismatic leaders is representative in
this regard. Weber employed a
leadership-centred approach to political thinking
and acting by viewing politics
as ‘the leadership or the influencing of the leadership
of a political association,
hence, today, of a state’; that is, a ‘human community that
(successfully) claims the
monopoly of the legitimate use of physical force within a
given territory’ (1946/1958,
77, 78). Asking the question about what makes people
obey authority, Weber
distinguishes between the cultural, social and psychological
sources of leaders’ powers.
Leadership, according to Weber, is exercised according
to traditional, legal-rational
or charismatic domination, authority and legitimation
(see Table 1.3; Weber 1986,
232–44). Weber’s typology of the most common
‘motors’ of leadership in
pre-modern and modern societies emphasizes leaders’
embeddedness in society and
helps solve research tasks of a comparative nature.
Karl Deutsch has offered a
typology of leaders based on the extent of leaders’
powers. Devised as a continuum
that ranges from strong, successful leaders to
relatively weak and
unsuccessful ones, Deutsch’s typology correlates key features
Table 1.2 Two Meanings of Good
Leadership
Good = Effective Ethical
Goals Balance of
realism and risk in vision Values of intentions, goals
Means Efficiency
of means to ends Quality of means used
Consequences Success in
achieving the group’s
goals
Good results for in-group and
outsiders
Source: Nye 2008, 112. By
permission of Oxford University Press. Inc. www.oup.com.
The Ashgate Research Companion
to Political Leadership
18
of the leader’s personality,
the type of support extended by the followers, and,
crucially, the fit between the
policies advocated by the leader and the prevailing
‘spirit of times’, or the
requirements of the historical situation that the leader can
ignore only at his or her own
peril (Table 1.4).
Oran Young has developed a
typology that is especially useful for the analysis
of leadership in international
relations. Building upon Max Weber’s classic scheme,
Young distinguished structural,
entrepreneurial, intellectual and charismatic
leadership in international
politics, especially with regard to regime formation and
institution building (Table
1.5).
Similarly, Robert Tucker (1981,
vii) followed in Weber’s footsteps, saying that
‘politics in its essential
nature is the leadership of a political community and all the
activity, including
participatory activity by citizens, that may enter into the process
of leadership’. Tucker
distinguished between enlightened leadership that was
characterized by its essential
commitment to moral humanism and responded to
global dangers in a responsible
way, on the one hand, and a form of anti-leadership
that did not rise to meet the
challenges of the Cold War, on the other hand. Tucker’s
typology therefore combined
empirical and normative elements.
Kellerman’s (2004)
functionalist typology is also of a mixed nature, particularly
in its emphasis on meaning
creation and the provision of certain public goods
by the leader. In classifying
the main functions of political leadership, Kellerman
underscores the functions of a
generally positive nature and broad social impact.
For Kellerman (2004), leaders
(a) create meaning and goals; (b) reinforce group
identity and cohesion; (c)
provide order; and (d) mobilize collective (adaptive) work
(21–5). It is fair to say that
most modern typologies of leadership seek to provide
Table 1.3 Weber’s Typology of
Legitimate Power/Authority
Type of legitimate
power/authority Source of legitimate power/authority
Traditional Custom, perennial
institutions
Rational-legal
Legal-bureaucratic procedures
Charismatic Personal qualities
(extraordinary ‘gifts’) of the leader
Source: Weber 1946/58.
Table 1.4 Strong versus Weak
Leaders
Leaders Personal
qualities
Type of support from followers
Fit between
leaders’ policies
and situations
Strong Strong, decisive
personality
A large group or coalition of
groups strongly
united with consistent bonds of
attitude and
interest
Fit
Weak Weak, indecisive
personality
Few supporters, or many
supporters who are
weakly united
Lack of fit
Source: Deutsch 1978.
Political Leadership in
Context
19
a convincing combination of
empirical and normative elements and pay special
attention to the wider social
impact and long-range consequences of leadership
activities.
On the other hand, Kellerman
constructed a very suggestive typology of
bad leadership based on
business and political case studies she had analyzed:
incompetent (Juan Antonio
Samaranch), rigid (Thabo Mbeki), intemperate (Boris
Yeltsin), callous (Martha
Stewart), corrupt (Diana (Dede) Brooks), insular (Bill
Clinton) and evil (Radovan
Karadzic, Pol Pot) (2004, 38–46). Kellerman did put
forward controversial
judgements, such as declaring former US President Bill
Clinton to have been an
insular, bad leader regarding the Rwandan genocide, and
only one category of badness
above the evil Radovan Karadzic and Pol Pot. Nye
says that Kellerman is correct
in a way, but overall circumstances were such that
Clinton could not have done
very much because of Congress’s unwillingness to
become involved in Africa after
the Somalian disaster, adding that ‘good leaders
today are often caught between
their cosmopolitan inclinations and their more
traditional obligations to the
followers who elected them’ (Nye 2008, 134).
The Authors’ Arguments
Molchanov reviews
historical-cultural traditions of leadership, as reflected in
religious and philosophical
texts from the Chinese, Indian, Judaic and Christian
canons. He notes that Eastern
thought has historically focused on the traditionalist,
collectivist, normative sides
of leadership, as distinguished from the individualist,
transformational visions in the
West. While criticizing the limitations of rational
individualism, Molchanov argues
for a creative synthesis of both Eastern and
Western traditions.
Myers sees dedication to
‘principle’ as a key element in political leadership.
His chapter examines the
postmodern challenge to principle and argues that the
postmodern attack suffers from
the limitations imposed by its own starting point
presented as a reaction to
‘modernity’. The most fruitful way to conserve principle,
while acknowledging what is
valid in the postmodern attack, is to return to the
Table 1.5 Synthesis of the
Leadership Typologies of Weber and Young
Source of power Position and
official
roles predominate
Personal qualities
predominate
Tradition X
Organization (rational-legal
authority) X
Public entrepreneurship X
Intellectual policy and strategic
vision X
Charisma X
Sources: Adapted from Weber
1946/1958, 232–3, and Young 1991.
The Ashgate Research Companion
to Political Leadership
20
approach of the pre-moderns,
the philosophers of Greek antiquity, starting with the
notion of prudence as an
ability to grasp the unique pattern of a specific situation.
Cornell and Malcolmson further
elaborate on this point. They argue that a prudent
leader possesses a repertoire
of models for imitation, through personal involvement
or the study of history, and
can apply those models to current circumstances to
judge what is important and
what is not, who can be persuaded and who cannot,
what has worked and what has
not. The authors address the practical question
of how one might apply
Machiavelli’s ideas on political leadership through an
examination of some of
Machiavelli’s key concepts, and they apply these concepts
to Shakespeare’s play Julius
Caesar as a case
study for a Machiavellian analysis.
Masciulli and Knight explore
leadership traits analysis and conceptions of
global political leadership.
They clarify four conceptions of global leadership – the
anti-leadership approach, as
well as democratic-idealist leadership, neoclassical
realist leadership and complex
liberal internationalist leadership. Masciulli and
Knight explore examples of
global leaders, especially the attributes of US President
Franklin Delano Roosevelt and
UN Secretary-Generals Dag Hammarskjold and
Kofi Annan.
Andrew’s chapter explores
Heidegger’s writings about Hitler’s leadership, and
Heidegger’s own proposed
leadership of the Nazi revolution in German universities
in the 1930s and 1940s.
Heidegger’s views are compared with Machiavelli’s claim
that ‘the people’ need
prophetic leaders in time of crisis, and Hegel’s and Marx’s
views on the relationship
between the masses and leaders.
Knight attempts to clarify the
meaning of leadership and management, as well
as their relationship in the
context of idealistic network theories of leadership. He
makes it clear that leaving out
the ethical and network dimensions are no longer
acceptable, either in terms of
ethics or effective organizational functioning.
Sjoberg argues that
ideal-typical understandings of leadership in global politics
are slanted toward recognizably
masculine characteristics. She critiques traditional
interpretations of who counts
as a leader and argues that the idea of leadership
itself will remain gendered for
as long as it rests on the notion of complete decisionmaking
autonomy of the competitive,
individualistic actor. In the concluding part
of her chapter, she proposes an
alternative feminist framework for the analysis of
leadership.
Corn and Jensen write about
civil–military relations in the American context and
more generally. DiPaolo’s
chapter probes the constitutional structures governing the
American president’s powers in
relation to defence and security. While presidential
leadership in times of war has
been aggrandized over the years, it is largely the
constitutional structure of
government that allows the executive to carve out more
authority in the face of
congressional silence or unwillingness to rein in presidential
power. This constitutional
structure is based on the Supreme Court’s decisions to
allow congressional deference
to executive authority during war.
Sykes, like Sjoberg, uses
gender analysis to show how traditional masculine
traits still permeate the
substance and the science of leadership. Sykes looks at
gendered constructs of
leadership in Anglo-American systems, drawing her
case studies from the
experience of women as national executives and members
Political Leadership in
Context
21
of cabinet. She discovers that
public expectations of female leaders considerably
differ from expectations that a
man would face in similar circumstances. Moreover,
institutional and ideological
changes affect men and women leaders in dissimilar
ways. Our theoretical
perspectives should therefore be reformed to account for
these differences. Sykes ends
her chapter by suggesting research strategies that
could be useful in this regard.
Two chapters by Lai and Chen
examine Chinese leadership in the context of
modernization, specifically
focusing on the so-called fourth generation of Chinese
communist leaders, the dilemmas
they face and the societal and global forces
that, at once, demand adaptive
and innovative responses from decision-makers in
Beijing and place considerable
constraints on their freedom of manoeuvre.
Gaman-Golutvina discusses
political leadership in Russia, focusing on socioeconomic
and organizational factors that
determined the evolution of the country’s
political elite. She compares
leadership styles and the qualities of the last Soviet
President, Mikhail Gorbachev,
and the first two post-Soviet Presidents, Boris Yeltsin
and Vladimir Putin. In all of
these instances, she notes the new and profound
significance of the leader’s
image, as constructed in the media and presented to the
people.
Modernization in a developing
society forms a backdrop for Mahdavi’s chapter,
which analyzes Islamic
leadership in general and Iranian political leadership in
particular.
Mazzucelli analyses the
creation and evolution of the Trio Presidency, seeking
to assess its potential to
satisfy the demand for consensual, shared leadership
in a larger European Union. She
examines such power instruments of the Trio
Presidency as privileged agenda
control and lobbying for institutional designs
that fit integration dynamics
well. The chapter seeks to establish whether the
requirements of increased
coordination within and between Trio Presidencies and
a particular rotation dynamic
envisioned for this institution will help to enhance
stability of leadership and
simultaneously avoid a concentration of agenda-shaping
powers. The chapter concludes
on an optimistic note: the very idea and the practice
of shared leadership, as
exemplified by the Trio Presidency, will work toward
bringing the EU governance
structure closer to the people.
Narine’s chapter examines
questions around political leadership in international
affairs and the recent spread
of human rights values. The chapter questions the
premise that international
human rights NGOs have led a normative revolution
on the issue of human rights.
Narine argues that recent actions by the West have
undermined the international
human rights movement. While many fear that
Western states are using the
‘human rights agenda’ as a camouflage for aggressive,
self-interested behaviour,
there is, as yet, no international consensus on the role of
human rights in international
conduct.
MacKinnon, Maybee, Molchanov
and Oldfield are more optimistic about
the leadership role and
capacity of non-governmental organizations. Taking
environmental and health NGOs
as a case study of leadership in such complex
global issues as the politics
of climate change, they argue that environmental
advocacy by non-governmental
organizations may, in fact, represent a successful
The Ashgate Research Companion
to Political Leadership
22
example of a rather unique
activity of ‘leading the leaders’. Convincing those with
the power to do the right thing
entails the whole host of specific interventions on the
part of NGOs: from framing the
issue to networking to influencing policy-makers
and monitoring policy
implementation. The chapter discusses specific features of
leadership in the voluntary
sector of society.
Both Bateman and Addicott
examine institutional conditions of leadership by
looking at legal frameworks and
judicial powers in particular. Institutions both
enable and constrain. In all
cases, institutions condition the exercise of political
leadership. Bateman examines
high court justices as political leaders, paying
particular attention to the
institutional constraints on judicial power. While the
concept of judicial power is
well established among students of law and politics,
much less attention has been
paid to the relationship between judicial power and
political leadership. Bateman’s
chapter explores a paradox at the heart of judicial
leadership: courts do it best
when they most persuasively seem not to be doing it
at all.
Addicott examines leadership in
times of war, focusing on the Bush
Administration’s War on Terror.
He suggests that in its effort to neutralize terrorist
threats at home and abroad, the
Bush Administration has been limited by legal
standards suited to interstate
conflict, not threats posed by loose networks of terrorist
cells using unconventional
weaponry. Bush’s political leadership challenge was to
navigate the US and the
international community through a new legal terrain, using
existing law where possible and
proposing new legal standards where necessary
and advantageous. Both essays
suggest that any account of political leadership
must consider legal and
institutional constraints and capacities.
Forbes tackles the problem of
the future education of political leaders – especially
in the context of the
discipline of political science. He examines the views of
prominent Canadian political
leaders on political education and, after a critique of
those views, advances his own
neo-Aristotelian perspective.
Carbert carries out a
political-economic analysis of rural women’s leadership,
using Canadian empirical data.
Her study suggests some interesting hypotheses
that could be pursued in
further empirical research.
Masciulli’s concluding chapter
recapitulates some of the key ideas of
previous chapters and explores
some future problems and prospects for political
leadership.
References
American Heritage Dictionary
of the English Language (1968) (Boston: Houghton
Mifflin). See ‘American
Heritage Biographies’.
Ammon, Royce J. (2001), Global
Television and the Shaping of World Politics: CNN,
Telediplomacy, and Foreign
Policy (Jefferson
NC: McFarland).
Aristotle (1958), The
Politics of Aristotle, trans. C. Lord (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press).
Political Leadership in
Context
23
——— (1958), The
Politics of Aristotle, trans. with Intro., notes and appendices by E.
Barker (New York: Oxford
University Press).
Baki, Vian, and David M. Barlow
(eds) (2007), Communication in the Age of Suspicion:
Trust and the Media (New York:
Palgrave Macmillan).
Bass, Bernard M. (1998), Transformational
Leadership: Industrial, Military and
Educational Impact (Mahwah
NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum).
——— (1990), Bass and
Stogdill’s Handbook of Leadership: Theory, Leadership, and
Managerial Applications, 3rd edn
(New York: Free Press).
——— (1985), Leadership
and Performance Beyond Expectations (New York: Free Press).
Bennis, Warren (2003), On
Becoming a Leader, 2nd edn (New York: Basic Books) (1st
edn 1989).
——— and Patricia W. Biederman
(1997), The
Secrets of Creative Collaboration (New
York: Perseus).
——— and Robert J. Thomas
(2002), Geeks and
Geezers: How Era, Values, and Defining
Moments Shape Leaders (Boston:
Harvard Business School Press).
Blondel, Jean (1987), Political
Leadership (London: Sage).
Bose, Meena (2006), ‘What Makes
a Great President? An Analysis of Leadership
Qualities in Fred I.
Greenstein’s The Presidential Difference’, in
Berman (ed.)
(2006), pp. 27–44.
Brysk, Alison (2002), Globalization
and Human Rights (Berkeley: University of
California Press).
Burns, James MacGregor (2003), Transforming
Leadership (New York: Atlantic
Monthly Press).
——— (1998), ‘Foreword’, in
Ciulla (ed.) (1998), pp. ix–xii.
——— (1978), Leadership
(New York:
Harper and Row).
———
and Susan Dunn (2001), The Three
Roosevelts: Patrician Leaders Who Transformed
America (New
York: Grove Press).
Byman,
Daniel, and Kenneth M. Pollack (2001), ‘Let Us Now Praise Great Men:
Bringing
the Statesman Back In’, International
Security, 25, 4, 107–46.
Carlyle,
Thomas (1993), On Heroes, Hero-Worship, and the
Heroic in History,
Introduction
and notes by Michael K. Goldbergl (Berkeley CA: University of
California
Press).
Ciulla,
Joanne B. (ed.) (2004a), Ethics:
The Heart of Leadership, 2nd edn
(Westport CT:
Praeger).
———
(ed.) (1998), Ethics: The Heart of Leadership, 1st edn (Westport CT: Quorum).
Coll,
Alberto R. (1995), ‘Normative Prudence as a Tradition of Statecraft’, in Joel
H.
Rosenthal
(ed.) (1995), Ethics and International Affairs:
A Reader (Washington DC:
Georgetown
University Press), pp. 58–77.
Dalai
Lama (1993), ‘Human Rights and Universal Responsibility’, speech delivered
at
the Forum of Non-Governmental Organizations, UN World Conference on
Human
Rights, Vienna, Austria, 15 June.
Deutsch,
Karl W. (1978), The Analysis of International
Relations, 2nd edn (Englewood
Cliffs
NJ: Prentice-Hall).
Drucker,
Peter F., with Joseph A. Maciariello (2006), Management, rev. edn (New
York:
Harper Collins).
The Ashgate Research Companion to Political Leadership
24
Eden,
Robert (1983), Political Leadership and
Nihilism: A Study of Weber and Nietzsche
(Tampa
FA: University Press of Florida).
Edersheim,
Elizabeth Hass (2007), The
Definitive Drucker (Toronto: McGraw-Hill).
Ferguson,
Niall (ed.) (1999), Virtual History: Alternatives and
Counterfactuals (New
York:
Perseus).
Fukuyama,
Francis (2002), Our Posthuman Future:
Consequences of the Biotechnology
Revolution (New
York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux).
Gaddis,
John Lewis (2005), Strategies of Containment: A
Critical Appraisal of American
National Security Policy During the Cold War, 2nd edn (New York: Oxford
University
Press).
George,
Alexander L., and Andrew Bennett (2005), Case
Studies and Theory
Development in the Social Sciences (Cambridge MA: MIT Press).
George,
Alexander L., and Juliette L. George (1998), Presidential
Personality and
Performance (Foreword
by Fred I. Greenstein) (Boulder CO: Westview).
Gergen,
David (2000), Eyewitness to Power: The Essence
of Leadership, Nixon to Clinton
(New
York: Simon & Schuster).
Grainger,
J.H. (2005), Tony Blair and the Ideal Type (Exeter: Imprint Academic).
Gramsci,
Antonio (1971), Selections from the Prison
Notebooks of Antonio Gramsci
(New
York: International).
Greenstein,
Fred (2006), ‘Plumbing the Presidential Psyche: Building on Neustadt
and
Barber’, in Larry Berman (ed.), The
Art of Political Leadership: Essays in Honor
of Fred I. Greenstein (New York: Rowman & Littlefield), pp. 17–26.
———
(2004), The Presidential Difference:
Leadership Style from FDR to George W. Bush
(Princeton
NJ: Princeton University Press).
———
(1988), ‘Dwight David Eisenhower: Leadership Theorist in the White
House’,
in Fred Greenstein (ed.), Leadership
in the Modern Presidency (Cambridge
MA:
Harvard University Press), pp. 76–107.
———
(1982), The Hidden-Hand Presidency:
Eisenhower as Political Leader (New
York:
Basic
Books).
Grint,
Keith (2005), Leadership: Limits and
Possibilities (New York: Macmillan).
———
(2000), The Arts of Leadership (New York: Oxford University Press).
———
(ed.) (1997), Leadership: Classical,
Contemporary, and Critical Approaches (New
York:
Oxford University Press).
Guntern,
Gottleib (ed.) (1997), The
Challenge of Creative Leadership (London:
Shepheard-Walwyn).
Habermas,
Jürgen (1971), Knowledge and Human Interests (Boston: Beacon).
Hamby,
Alonzo (2006), ‘Leadership, Charisma, and Political Cultures in the Great
Depression:
Adolf Hitler, Franklin Roosevelt, and Stanley Baldwin’, in Larry
Berman
(ed.), The Art of Political Leadership:
Essays in Honor of Fred I. Greenstein
(New
York: Rowman & Littlefield), pp. 17–26.
Harvard Business Review on Leadership (1998) (Boston: Harvard Business School
Press).
Havel,
Vaclav (1990), Disturbing the Peace: A
Conversation with Karel Hvizdala (New
York:
Knopf).
Hay,
Colin (2002), Political Analysis: A Critical
Introduction (New York: Palgrave).
Political Leadership in Context
25
———
(1995), ‘Structure and Agency’, in David Marsh and Gerry Stoker (eds),
Theory and Methods in Political Science, 1st edn (New York: St Martin’s Press), pp.
192–206.
Heifetz,
Ronald A. (1994), Leadership Without Easy Answers (Cambridge MA:
Harvard
University Press/Belknap Press).
Hodgkinson,
Christopher (1983), The Philosophy of Leadership (New York: St Martin’s
Press).
Hollander,
Edwin, (1998), ‘Ethical Challenges in the Leader–Follower Relationship’,
in
Ciulla (ed.) (1998).
Hook,
Sidney (1943), The Hero in History: A Study of
Limitation and Possibility (New
York:
John Day Company).
House,
Robert J., Paul J. Hanges, Mansour Javidan, Peter W. Dorfman and Vipin
Gupta
(eds) (2004), Culture, Leadership, and
Organizations: The GLOBE Study of 62
Societies (Thousand
Oaks CA: Sage).
Hunt,
Sonja (1984), ‘The Role of Leadership in the Construction of Reality’, in B.
Kellerman
(ed.), Leadership: Multidisciplinary
Perspectives (Princeton NJ: Prentice-
Hall),
pp. 157–78.
Ignatieff,
Michael (2004), The Lesser Evil: Political
Ethics In An Age of Terror (Toronto:
Penguin).
Jones,
Brian D. (ed.) (1989), Leadership
and Politics: New Perspectives in Political Science
(Lawrence
KA: University Press of Kansas).
Keck,
Margaret E., and Kathryn Sikkink (1998), Activists
Beyond Borders: Advocacy
Networks in International Politics (Ithaca NY: Cornell University Press).
Kegley,
Charles W. Jr. (1995b), Controversies
in International Relations Theory: Realism
and the NeoLiberal Challenge (New York: St Martin’s Press).
Kellerman,
Barbara (2008), Followership (Boston: Harvard Business School Press).
———
(2004), Bad Leadership: What it is, How
it Happens, Why it Matters (Boston:
Harvard
Business School Press).
———
(1999), Reinventing Leadership: Making
the Connection Between Politics and
Business (Albany:
State University of New York Press).
———
(1986), Political Leadership: A Source
Book (Pittsburgh: University of
Pittsburgh
Press).
———
(ed.) (1984), Leadership: Multidisciplinary
Perspectives (Englewood Cliffs NJ:
Prentice
Hall).
King,
Anthony (2002), Leaders’ Personalities and the
Outcomes of Democratic Elections
(New
York: Oxford University Press).
Kissinger,
Henry (1974), American Foreign Policy: Expanded
Edition (New York:
Norton).
Klenke,
Karin (1996), Women and Leadership: A
Contextual Perspective (New York:
Springer).
Kouzes,
James M., and Barry Z. Posner (eds) (2007), The
Leadership Challenge, 4th
edn
(San Francisco: Wiley).
Lane,
Robert E. (2003), ‘Epilogue: Rescuing Political Science from Itself’, in David
O.
Sears, Leonie Huddy and Robert Jervis (eds), Oxford
Handbook of Political
Psychology (New
York: Oxford University Press), pp. 755–93.
The Ashgate Research Companion to Political Leadership
26
Lauren,
Paul Gordon, Gordon A. Craig, and Alexander George (2007), Force
and Statecraft: Diplomatic Challenges of Our Time, 4th edn (New York: Oxford
University
Press).
Lenin,
Vladimir Ilyich (2007) [1914], Conspectus of Hegel’s Science of Logic – Book
I
(The Doctrine of Being), ed. Stewart Smith. Lenin Internet Archive, at:
www.marxists.org/archive/lenin/works/1914/cons-logic/ch01.htm#f46r>.
———
(1975), The Lenin Anthology, ed. Robert C. Tucker (New York: Norton).
Lord,
C. (2003), The Modern Prince: What Leaders
Need to Know Now (New Haven and
London:
Yale University Press).
Machiavelli,
Niccolò (1989), The Prince, trans. Leo Paul S. de Alvarez (Prospect
Heights
IL: Waveland Heights). (Orig. written 1513; first publ. 1532.)
Mant,
Alistair (1999), Intelligent Leadership, 2nd edn (London: Allen & Unwin).
March,
James G., and Thierry Weil (2005), On
Leadership (Oxford: Blackwell).
Marsh,
David (2002), ‘Marxism’, in David Marsh and Gerry Stoker (eds), Theory and
Methods in Political Science (New York: Palgrave).
Masciulli,
Joseph, and Richard B. Day (2006), ‘Governing a Global Community of
Shared
Risks’, in Richard B. Day and Joseph Masciulli (eds), Globalization and
Political Ethics (Leiden:
Brill), pp. 681–706.
Mearsheimer,
John J. (2001), The Tragedy of Great Power
Politics (New York: Norton).
Michels,
Robert (1986), ‘The Impossibility of Direct Government’, in Kellerman
(ed.),
pp. 177–91.
Miller,
David (2007), ‘Introduction’, in Walzer (2007), pp. vii–xi.
Northouse,
Peter G. (2004), Leadership: Theory and Practice, 3rd edn (Thousand Oaks
CA:
Sage).
Nye,
Joseph Jr (1999), ‘New Models of Public Leadership’, in Frances Hesselbein,
Marshall
Goldsmith and Iain Somerville (eds), Leading
Beyond the Walls (San
Francisco:
Jossey-Bass).
———
(2008), The Powers to Lead (New York: Oxford University Press).
Peele,
Gillian (2005), ‘Leadership and Politics: A Case for a Closer Relationship?’
Leadership,
1, 2, 187–204.
Post,
Jerrold M. (2004), Leaders and Their Followers in a
Dangerous World: The
Psychology of Political Behavior (Ithaca NY: Cornell University Press).
Rawls,
John (1999), A Theory of Justice, rev. edn (Cambridge MA: Harvard University
Press).
Rejai,
Mustafa, and Kay Phillips (2002), Concepts
of Leadership in Western Political
Thought (Westport
CT: Praeger).
Rousseau,
Jean-Jacques (1987), Basic Political Writings, trans. and ed. Donald A.
Cress
(Indianapolis: Hackett).
Ruggie,
John G. (1998), Constructing the World Polity (London and New York:
Routledge).
Scott,
W. Richard (2001), ‘The Corporate Practice of Medicine: Competition and
Innovation
in Health Care’, Journal of Health Politics,
Policy and Law, 26, 3 (June),
655–7.
Service,
Robert (2000), Lenin – A Biography (Cambridge MA: Harvard University
Press).
Political Leadership in Context
27
Shambaugh,
David (ed.) (1995), Deng Xiaoping: Portrait of a
Chinese Statesman (New
York:
Oxford University Press).
Shapiro,
Ian (2007), The Flight from Reality in the
Human Sciences (Princeton NJ:
Princeton
University Press).
Sheffer,
Gabriel (ed.) (1993), Innovative Leaders in
International Politics (Albany:
State
University
of New York Press).
Shriberg,
Arthur, David L. Shribert and Richa Kumari (2005), Practicing Leadership:
Principles and Applications (New York: Wiley).
Singer,
Peter (2004), One World: The Ethics of
Globalization, 2nd edn (New Haven:
Yale
University Press).
Stier,
Mark (1997), ‘The Whole Truth and Nothing But the Truth? Deception and
the
Educative Ideal of Politics’, in Laura Duhan Kaplan and Lawrence F. Bove
(eds),
Philosophical Perspectives on
Power and Domination (Amsterdam: Rodopi),
pp.
115–132.
Takala,
T. (1997), ‘Charismatic Leadership: A Key Factor in Organizational
Communication’,
Corporate Communication – An
International Journal, 1, 8–14.
Tucker,
Robert C. (1995), Politics as Leadership, 2nd edn (Columbia MO: University
of
Missouri Press).
———
(1981), Politics as Leadership (Columbia MO: University of Missouri Press).
———
(1987), Political Culture and Leadership
in the USSR: From Lenin to Gorbachev
(New
York: Norton).
———
(1977a), ‘Personality and Political Leadership’, Political Science Quarterly, 92,
3,
383–93.
Waltz,
Kenneth (1959), Man, the State and War: A
Theoretical Analysis (New York:
Columbia
University Press).
———
(1979), Theory of International Politics (New York: Random House).
Walzer,
Michael (2007), Thinking Politically: Essays in
Political Theory, ed. David
Miller
(New Haven: Yale University Press).
———
(1992), Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral
Argument with Historical Illustrations,
2nd
edn (New York: Basic).
Weber,
Max (1986), ‘Types of Authority’, in Kellerman (ed.) (2006).
———
(1946/1958), From Max Weber: Essays in
Sociology, ed. H.H. Gerth and C.
Wright
Mills (New York: Oxford University Press).
Wildavsky,
Aaron (2006), Cultural Analysis, ed. Brendon Swedlow, Dennis Coyle,
Richard
Ellis, Robert Kagan and Austin Ranney (New Brunswick: Translation).
———
(1989), ‘A Cultural Theory of Leadership’, in Bryan D. Jones (ed.), Leadership
and Politics: New Perspectives in Political Science (Lawrence: University Press of
Kansas),
pp. 87–113.
Young,
Oran R. (1991), ‘Political Leadership and Regime Formation: On the
Development
of Institutions in International Society’, International
Organization,
45,
3 (Summer), 281–308.
Yukl,
Gary (2009), Leadership in Organizations, 7th edn (New York: Pearson
Education).
No comments:
Post a Comment